Psychology as a Science
The title of this course is “Psychology as a Science”
But what is this thing called “Science”?
Is it a special way of learning about the world?
And if so, then what makes it special?
The common-sense view might go something like this:
Science is special because it’s knowledge based on facts
Science is often contrasted with other forms of knowledge that might be:
But this raises two questions:
The common-sense view of science was formalised by two schools of thought: The empiricists and the positivists
Together they held a view that went something like this:
Knowledge should be derived from the facts of experience
We can break this idea down:
Careful and unbiased observers can directly access facts through the senses/observation.
Facts come before and are independent of, theories.
Facts form a firm and reliable base for scientific knowledge.
But is this true?
A simple story of how the senses work might go like this: There are some external physical causes (light, sound waves etc.) that produce some physical changes in our sense organs (e.g., our eyes) that are then registered by the brain.
This account implies direct and unmediated access to the world through our senses. But is this actually the case?
The previous example is just a toy example, but it reveals a larger point:
Two scientists might “observe” something different even when looking at the same thing.
In some fields, being able to make “observations” actually requires training. For example,
Training in how to observe stuff through a microscope
Training in how to distinguish different kinds of behaviour
Training in how to read an x-ray
So a simple claim that observations are “unbiased” or “straightforwardly given by the senses” seems to be false.
When we think of a “fact” there are two things we could mean
“Fact” could refer to some external state of the world
Or “fact” could refer to statements about those external states
The fact that this university is in East Sussex could refer to this actual university and its actual being in East Sussex
or it could refer to the statement: “This university is in East Sussex.”
When we talk about “facts” as the basis for science, we’re talking about these statements.
We’ll call this type of fact an “observation statement.”
Think of a child learning the word apple:
They might initially imitate the word “apple” when shown an apple by their parent.
Next, they might use the word “apple” when pointing to apples.
But then one day they might see a tennis ball and say “apple”. The parent would then correct them, and show them that a tennis ball isn’t an apple because you can’t, for example, bite into it like an apple.
By the time the child can make accurate “observation statements” about the presence of apples they might already know a lot about the properties of apples (have an extensive “theory of apples”)
The same goes for scientists: formulating observation statements might require substantial background knowledge or a conceptual framework to place them in.
They aren’t completely independent of theory.
Let’s say that we’ve been able to acquire some facts. Will any old facts do?
Let’s take a simple example:
You observe that grass grows longer among the cowpats in a field.
You think this is because the dung traps moisture that helps the grass grow.
Your friend thinks this is because the dung acts as a fertiliser.
Observations alone can’t distinguish these. To tell which is correct you need to intervene on the situation.
For example, grind up the dung so that it still fertilises the ground or use something else to trap the moisture.
Intervening, for example, through experiment allows you to tell what the relevant facts of your observation are.
By intervening on the system, we can tell which facts are relevant
But scientific theories may play a part in helping to determine what is and isn’t relevant
An example from the history of cognitive psychology:
In certain kinds of reading tasks psychologists thought it was relevant that people made errors, but they didn’t think the exact nature of the errors was relevant.
But after certain kinds of theories were developed (ones based on neural network models) they came to realise that the particular kinds of errors (e.g., if people swapped letters between words) was relevant.
In short, observations can’t be completely divorced from theories.
And experiments will presume the truth of certain theories (e.g., brain imaging experiments assume the validity of certain theories about brain function).
Facts don’t care about your feelings
— Guy on the internet
The idea that science is objective in a simple sense of “objectivity” is misleading.
Your conceptual framework, and theoretical assumptions, and even your knowledge and training can play a part in what kinds of observations you can make or what types of observation statements you can formulate
“Objectivity” doesn’t mean observations free from theoretical assumptions (“the view from nowhere”)
“Objectivity” does mean:
Publicly and independently verifiable methods
Recognising theoretical assumptions
Theory/data that are open to revision and improvement
Free from avoidable forms of bias (confounds, cherry picking data, experimenter bias)
It is also objective in the sense that despite all this, when you make the observations either the behaviour will happen or it won’t, the detector will flash, or it won’t etc. Your theory can’t make things happen.
The final part of the common-sense view of science is that scientific knowledge is derived from facts.
Usually this idea of derived means something like logically derived. We might sum up the view like this:
Science = Facts + Logic
— Guy on the internet
To understand what it might mean to logically derive scientific knowledge we need to know a bit about logic.
A deductive argument is called valid if the conclusions follow from the premises.
Example 1
In this example, if we accept that (1) and (2) are true, then we have to accept (3) as true. We cannot accept (1) and (2) as true and then deny that (3) is true because we would be contradicting ourselves.
Example 2
In our new example, we can accept (1) and (2) as true without accepting (3) as true. That is, (3) does not necessarily follow from (1) and (2). It might just be a case of a research methods lecture that isn’t boring.
Deduction is only concerned with whether (3) follows from (1) and (2). It is not concerned with determining whether (1) and (2) are true or false. The argument assumes that (1) and (2) are true, but it doesn’t establish truth
Example 3
The conclusion is valid. However, it is also false because (1) is false.
It is valid because if we accept (1) and (2) we have to accept (3)
Logic only tells us what follows from what. If there is truth in our premises, then there is truth in our conclusions.
If our premises are false, then our conclusions will also be false.
Deductive logic is truth-preserving, but it can’t tell us what is true and what is false. The conclusion is just a re-statement of the information contained in the premises
So deductive logic can’t create new knowledge. What we you do instead?
We need a way to go from particular observations to generalizations
The process of induction allows us to construct arguments of the following form:
Premises
Conclusion
All swans are white
But the problem with arguments like this is that all the premises may be true and yet the conclusion can be false.
Maybe we just haven’t observed the one swan that isn’t white?
But surely there are good and bad inductive arguments?
More observations are better than fewer observations—but how many is enough?
Observations in many different contexts—but what makes a context different and what makes differences relevant?
No contradicting observations—but what about probabilistic phenomena?
Clear and simple rules aren’t easy to come by.
But the bigger problem is induction can never establish truth.
So how do we ever prove anything for certain in science. The short answer is, we don’t.
We can never be certain of truth.
Instead of just collecting confirmations we can employ induction and deduction together
Collect observations and use induction to come up with general laws and theories from particular observations
Use deduction to figure out what logically follows from these general laws and theories
This approach nicely captures the idea of testability
Our theories should make predictions about what we expect to find, and we can test these predictions with more observations
The philosopher Karl Popper saw trouble with relying on induction. He wanted to put science on a firmer logical footing.
He proposed that while you can’t use deduction to figure out what is true, you can use deduction to figure out what is false
He said a key quality of scientific theories is that they should be falsifiable
Theories can come into existence through any means (wild speculation, guesses, dreams, or whatever), but once a theory has been proposed it has to be rigorously and ruthlessly tested
Confirmation
Premise: A swan that was white was spotted in London at time t
Conclusion: All swans are white.
The conclusion might be true or false, but it doesn’t logically follow from the premise
Falsification
Premise: A swan, which was not white, was spotted in Australia at time t.
Conclusion: Not all swans are white.
The conclusion logically follows from the premise, so if the premise is true the conclusion is true.
We can’t prove the claim “all swans are white”, but we can reject it
That is, we can show that the claim “all swans are white” is false
Good theories are falsifiable, better theories are more falsifiable
Three theories:
Of these three theories, (1) is the least falsifiable and (3) is the most falsifiable. Why? For theory (1) only an observation of Mars could falsify it. But for theory (3), an observation of Mars, Venus, Saturn, Neptune, or any other yet undiscovered planet would falsify it.
Bad theories are ones that can seemingly accommodate any observation
If two outcomes are possible and the theory can explain outcome one and outcome two then this is bad. What would be evidence against the theory?
Good theories are broad in their applicability but precise in their predictions
What happens when you make an observation that falsifies a theory?
That is, you observe something that contradicts the theory you’re testing. What do you do?
Your options:
You could abandon the theory
But what about probabilistic theories?
And what about auxiliary assumptions?
You could modify or amend the theory
Theories in psychology tend to be probabilistic. They make claims about how things are on average, not claims about how things are in every case.1
Much of what we do with statistics is figuring out how to test and specify probabilistic claims. For example:
But putting that aside, a single contradictory observation can’t falsify a probabilistic claim because we will sometimes expect contradictions with probabilistic claims.
Putting aside the probabilistic nature of claims (or assuming you’ve seen enough contradictory examples), should these contradictory observations lead you to abandon the theory?
Experiments don’t test one theory in isolation, but rely on a range of auxiliary assumptions and other support theories.
For example, an experiment on memory using brain imaging is also making assumptions about the truth of theories related to:
The physics of how brain imaging machines work
Theories about how brains work by, for example, requiring oxygen during neural processing
And possibly many other theories
It may be the case that what is actually at fault is one of these auxiliary assumptions and not your theory
Telling which part of the interconnected web of theories is at fault can be tricky. Philosophers call this the Duhem-Quine problem.
Popper didn’t have a good answer on how to figure out where to lay the blame for an apparent falsification.
But he thought that theories shouldn’t be abandoned too quickly.
He suggested some dogmatism, because at the start scientists might still be figuring out the details, and therefore they might just need to make some tweaks and modify their theories instead of abandoning them
But if we decide to amend a theory, then how do we do this?
Theory: All bread is nourishing
Observation: Bread eaten in a French village in 1951 was not nourishing1
Ad-hoc modification
All bread except bread eaten in a French village in 1951 is nourishing
Modification has fewer tests: Original theory can be tested by eating any bread. Modified theory can be tested by eating any bread except that particular bread.
Acceptable modification
All bread except bread made with flour containing ergot fungus is nourishing
Modification leads to new tests: 1) Test the bread for the presence of fungus; 2) Cultivate fungus and make bread with it and test whether it nourishes; 3) Analyse fungus for poisons, etc
Popper’s focus on falsifying theories leads to a couple of problems:
It can be difficult to figure out when to abandon theories and when to amend theories.
It can be difficult to compare two theories to see which is “better”
The philosopher Imre Lakatos developed his idea of research programmes1 as a reaction to these two problems.
One key aspect of Lakatos’s idea of research programmes is that not all parts of a science are on par
Some laws or principles are so fundamental they might be considered a defining part of the science.
Other parts might be more peripheral
Lakatos called these fundamental parts the hard core and the more peripheral parts the protective belt
He suggested that the hard core is resistant to falsification, so when an apparent falsifier is observed the blame is placed on theories in the protective belt
Research programmes are defined by what is in their hard core
What is in the hard core and what is in the protective belt might not always be explicit, but these might be some examples:
In Cognitive Science the hard core might include the theory that the mind/brain is a particular kind of computational system and the protective belt might include specific theories about how memory works
In the biomedical view of mental illness the hard core might include the theory that mental illness can be explained biochemically and the protective belt might include the dopamine theory of schizophrenia
When apparent falsifications occur the protective belt is up for revision but the hard core stays intact. Falsifying the hard core amounts to abandoning the research programme (more on this later)
On Lakatos’s view, scientists work within a research programme.
He split guidelines for working within a research programme into a negative and positive heuristic, specifying what scientists shouldn’t do but also what they should do
The negative heuristic includes things like not abandoning the hard core
The positive heuristic is harder to specify exactly, but it includes suggestions on how to supplement the protective belt to develop the research programme further
That is, it should specify a programme of research
The research programme should identify problems to solve
Lakatos was also interested in comparing research programmes, something that is difficult to do on a strictly falsificationist account.
He divided research programmes into those that are progressive and those that are degenerating
Progressive research programmes are coherent (i.e., have minimal contradictions)
And progressive research programmes make novel predictions that follow naturally from theories that are part of the programme
These predictions are then confirmed by experiments
Degenerating research programmes are those that have faced so many falsifications that they have been modified to the point of being incoherent
When the hard core is abandoned then scientists move from one research programme into a new one.
Some examples of this in psychology might include:
The move from psychological behaviourism to cognitive science
From classical cognitive science to embodied cognitive science
From connectionism to deep neural networks
From sociobiology to evolutionary psychology
But again, what is and isn’t a research programme isn’t always clear, because often the hard core and the protective belt are left implicit and not made explicit
However, I think it’s valuable to keep these distinctions in mind as you move through your university career
In thinking about the nature of science, the status of science, and the processes we use to create and justify knowledge, there are a lot of things to talk about.
This one course doesn’t have time to do them all justice.
In particular, I would’ve liked to talk about Feminist perspectives on science, the status of indigenous epistemologies (theories of knowledge), and how race, racism, and colonialism impact science.
If any of these topics interest you check out the links in the handout